Friday, May 23, 2014

Chapter 4: Introducing Ecumenical Expressivism


Chapter 4, ‘Introducing Ecumenical Expressivism’, packs in a lot of stimulating ideas that are central to the broader project of the book, so I’m afraid this summary will be a bit longer than ideal. Let’s start with a quick recap: Chapter 2 argued that normative thought is affective, action-guiding, and acrimonious, and that these features militate against understanding it as being purely representational. Chapter 3 made the case that the core features can’t be captured by adding a desire-like element to representational content. This points us in the direction of expressivism, the subject matter of the chapter at hand. For expressivists, normative thoughts are in the first instance constituted by desire-like states, and are as such inherently practical. This gives it an edge when it comes to accounting for the affective and action-guiding aspects of normative thought. Insofar as normative disagreement is best understood as disagreement in attitude, this also favours expressivism. The distinctive claim of ecumenical expressivism is that normative judgment is a hybrid state consisting of a desire-like element and a suitably related representational belief. In this central chapter, Ridge explains what exactly the hybrid state is, and argues that the meanings of normative terms are explained in terms of the mental states they express.

Procedural note: I wrote this critical summary on the basis of an earlier draft of the book, which was organized differently. Since I don’t think the order affects the points made below, I’ll leave it as it is.

Normative Thought

Ridge labels the desire-like component of a normative judgment the agent’s normative perspective. For Gibbard, it would consist in states of norm-acceptance, but Ridge prefers a Bratmanian picture, on which a normative perspective is a “set of relatively stable policies against accepting certain standards of deliberation” (115), in particular policies the agent is satisfied with (roughly in the sense of not having conflicting policies). Policies here are kind of general contingency plans, in particular plans about how to deliberate. (For Bratman, self-governing policies are plans about which desires to treat as providing justifying reasons, but Ridge rightly eschews appeal to unanalysed notions treating something as a reason.) So when you have a normative perspective, you plan (that is, intend) not to deliberate in certain ways. Perhaps you intend not to be the kind of person for whom the colour of another’s skin is an important consideration in deciding whether to pursue friendship. (This is not how Ridge puts it, but since I worry about the notion of a standard here (see below), I’m suggesting an alternative gloss in the spirit of the view, as I understand it.)

But surely there’s more to normative thought than settling on not deliberating in certain ways! Ridge agrees. Our normative perspectives are also constituted by plans to act and deliberate in ways that are required or highly recommended by all the standards we have not ruled out (any acceptable standards). They also involve a defeasible propensity to encourage others to do likewise. (Think back on Stevenson: “I approve of this; do so as well”.)

So that, very roughly, is the desire-like aspect of normative judgment for Ridge. The judgment itself consists of a combination of normative perspective with a relevant representational belief. What representational belief? Here we go back to Chapter 1 and the idea that any normative judgment can be understood in terms of something being highly ranked or required or recommended by contextually determined standards. Suppose Anne thinks that pleasure is good as an end. According to Ridge’s analysis, this amounts to her thinking that pleasure would be highly ranked as an end by any ultimate acceptable standard of practical reasoning. And this thought, in turn, has the following two elements (cf. 119):

a)     A normative perspective.
b)    The representational belief that pleasure would be highly ranked as an end by any admissible ultimate standard of practical reasoning.

So, roughly, you accept certain standards of practical reasoning, and believe that those standards rank pleasure highly as an end. That’s what it is to think that pleasure is good as an end. On this view, a normative judgment is a relational state in the sense that Mark Schroeder has popularized, since the content of the belief refers to the content of the normative perspective (‘admissible’ standards in b are those not ruled out in a). The core appeal of thinking of normative judgments as this sort of hybrid states is that they allow for any degree of logical complexity in the content of the belief element, which helps deal with some key objections to expressivism (see next chapter).

Okay, so much for a very brief sketch of the view. I have four questions or worries. First, it’s not clear what the role of the representational belief is in normative judgment. Return to the case of thinking that pleasure is good as an end. Evidently, Anne’s normative perspective consists of policies ruling out standards that rule out pleasure as an end, and plans to give pleasure positive weight as an end in practical reasoning. Question: why does that not suffice, for an expressivist in particular, for her judging that pleasure is good as an end? If all the standards she endorses rank pleasure highly, why does she also have to believe that admissible standards rank pleasure highly? After all, the distinctively normative aspect of the thought is all in the attitudes, for an expressivist. To be sure, the hybrid model makes sense when it comes to, say, thoughts of good bread. It’s plausible enough that one way in which the thought that O’Keeffe’s bread is good can be realized is that I accept only standards for choosing bread that rank crustiness highly, and believe that O’Keeffe’s bread is crusty. But what about the thoughts that are not of this type?

Second, since the expressivist project is to explain normative thought without appeal to normative content (which will be downstream from normative thought), there’s always the question of whether an expressivist account is necessary and sufficient for normative judgment. Since Ridge packs a lot into the notion of a normative perspective, the necessity question is particularly urgent for his view. Do we really have to manifest such complex intentions and beliefs in order to think, say, that we have a reason to go swimming on a hot day? This isn’t just a point about the mind-boggling psychological complexity of Ridge’s view. It is rather that it seems possible to make normative judgments that don’t involve stable policies of any sort, not to mention stable policies regarding standards of practical reasoning. Why wouldn’t it be possible?

Third, what about sufficiency? Recall that normative perspectives are essentially sets of complex conditional intentions. The question is whether combining such planning states with representational beliefs is enough for a normative judgment. Clearly, we can intend to do something without judging that we ought to do it, or have reason to do it. So why can’t we intend to (not to) deliberate in a certain way without thinking that we ought to do so, or that we ought to act in a certain way? On this point, the contrast between Gibbard’s and Ridge’s views is instructive. On Gibbard’s original view, moral judgment consists of accepting norms for guilt and anger. Although there’s room to question the sufficiency of that, it’s at least plausible that endorsing reactive attitudes is closely bound up with moral (and perhaps more broadly normative) judgment. But for Ridge, emotions are only contingently linked with normative judgment. So all the weight is borne by policies for deliberating. And on the face of it, it seems I could have a policy of giving positive weight to X in deliberation (including rejecting standards for deliberating that don’t give X positive weight) without thereby thinking that X is good or that I have reason to X (especially if we understand giving positive weight in naturalistic terms, as something a robot might do).

My fourth, and possibly related, worry about Ridge’s account is that I’m not sure if it goes deep enough. Take again Gibbard’s original view for comparison. Accepting a norm requiring X-ing is, roughly, being motivated to X and perhaps feeling bad if one doesn’t X, and being disposed to communicate this state of mind to others when speaking without openly. So all we have is attitudes and behavioural dispositions whose object is an unambiguously factual (X-ing, speaking in a certain way). This is a clearly naturalistic, non-normative account of what it is to think normative thoughts. Ridge’s view, in what seems to me to be an important contrast, is spelled out in terms of commitments whose content involves reference to what is required or recommended by a standard. To my eyes, that’s normative talk, something the expressivist needs to analyse away in terms of attitudes toward natural facts. It’s not enough to know that in making a normative judgment, we’re committed to a standard that requires X-ing. We need to know, in terms that don’t make reference to “standards” or “requiring”, what attitudes we must have toward X-ing in order to have such commitment. This is even more urgent when it comes to beliefs about standards requiring or recommending or highly ranking something – what is it to believe such a thing?


Normative Language

So much for a brief characterization of ecumenical expressivism as a theory of normative thought. But what about normative language? It’s not clear, Ridge observes, what question expressivism is trying to answer when it promises to account for the meaning of normative language. There’s two main options. A semantic theory for a language consists of two main parts: an assignment of semantic values to the terms and a syntax that tells us how to derive semantic values of wholes from the semantic values of parts and the way they’re arranged. A meta-semantic theory, in Ridge’s terms, explains why terms have the meanings they do. Mark Schroeder thinks of expressivism as a first-order semantic theory, according to which the contents (or semantic values) of normative sentences are mental states. But Ridge argues that expressivism is best understood as a view in meta-semantics instead.

What does this mean? First, expressivism is compatible with standard first-order semantics for normative sentences. So the expressivist will agree that “Abortion is wrong” is true iff abortion is wrong, or if the referent of “abortion” is in the extension of the predicate “morally wrong”. Here terms like “truth” and “referent” are used in a deflationary sense that doesn’t entail that there is, say, the property of wrongness out there. (Making this contrast is notoriously hard once you go deflationist about everything, but you get the point.) Second, what is distinctive about expressivism is the meta-semantic thesis it advances: normative claims have the meanings they do in virtue of their expressing normative judgments, which are hybrid states of the sort discussed above.

Ridge labels the broader Lockean/Gricean metasemantic framework in which meanings of linguistic items are explained by way of the mental states they express ideationalism. Words mean what they do, because they are conventionally used to express certain states of mind. What is it to ‘express’ a state of mind? Ridge sketches two options. The first, based on Wayne Davis’s work, is that a word expresses an idea if it conventionally indicates it. (Presumably Davis explains what an ‘idea’ is – on the face of it, this suggestion is highly implausible, as the basic units of communication are sentences rather than words, and they express complex, highly unconventional thoughts rather than individual ideas.) The other is that sentences express those thoughts that people who assert them are accountable for having. For example, if you assert “There’s cheese on the moon”, you’re accountable for having the belief that there’s cheese on the moon, on pain of being charged with insincerity or semantic confusion by other members of your linguistic community. Like Ridge, I find the latter account of expression more promising – but it’s not immediately clear how it links up with the core claim that meanings are explained by the mental states they express. It’s certainly compatible with non-ideationalist meta-semantic frameworks.

Ridge does, however, provide a story of how the meta-semantic explanation works – how the mental state that a sentence expresses explains its propositional content (i.e. the proposition it expresses, in a different sense of ‘express’). Importantly, propositions here cannot be understood in standard Fregean or Russellian or Lewisian sense, as abstract entities or structured entities composed of individuals and properties or sets of possible worlds. If they were, normative propositions could be the contents of standard representational beliefs, and the contents of normative claims could be explained by virtue of what they represent, as cognitivists maintain. So Ridge has to cast about for an alternative conception of propositions, and finds one in Scott Soames’s work. Soames argues that propositions are cognitive event types. On this view, a belief that X is F, say, isn’t a relation to an abstract entity (for example) with the content that X is F. Instead, it is a cognitive event that consists of predicating F of X (where predication is a primitive contentful mental act) and some sort of endorsement of this predication. Propositions are types of basic cognitive events (such as predications).

Soames’s view is an account of propositions as bearers of representational content. But Ridge maintains that this approach generalizes naturally to normative thoughts. They, too, are cognitive events of various cognitive types. Normative propositions are, then, cognitive types of a particular kind – types of practical thought. Ridge claims that “we can have normative propositions in precisely Soames’s sense. For once we allow that thinking that abortion is morally wrong is a cognitive event, we can plausibly infer that there is a corresponding cognitive event type, and so on for all such normative thoughts.” (129)

But is this really sufficient? Sure, hybrid states form cognitive types. But central to Soames’s case for identifying propositions with cognitive event types is that cognitive events of predication (in particular) are primitively representational (and have inherent truth conditions), unlike abstract objects (Fregean propositions). But hybrid states are not primitively representational – they’re not representational at all! So I don’t see how following Soames’s arguments would get us to normative propositions consisting of essentially non-cognitive event types.

Putting that worry aside, Ridge believes that this understanding of propositions allows for a distinctively expressivist metasemantics. On this view, giving the semantic content of a claim consists of “articulating the proposition it expresses in some privileged language” (130). (Is this really all that first-order semantics does?) Since normative propositions are types of hybrid states, “what it is for a proposition p to be expressed by a claim in a context of utterance is for that claim to express the thought that p, where the proposition that p just is the cognitive event type of thinking that p” (130).

There is evidently much more to be said here, but I’ll leave it for general discussion. Here’s a final thought. It seems that expressivism faces a kind of dilemma: either it is committed to non-standard, non-truth conditional semantics, or it is committed to a controversial meta-semantic framework and a highly controversial account of propositions (which does not obviously fit with the expressivist strategy). (Officially, Ridge says that ideationalism is the “most natural home” for expressivism, but it’s hard to see how the strategy would work in other metasemantic frameworks.) Either way, it seems that accounting for normative language in terms of essentially non-representational states is not good for your plausibility points, unless you belong to the small set of people who are antecedently both ideationalist and Soamesian.

Tuesday, May 13, 2014

Chapter 3: Ecumenical Cognitivism


In chapter 3, Ridge discusses ecumenical cognitivist views, which, on his view (see the intro, pages 7 and 11), have some (relatively) promising resources with regard to accounting for the continuities and discontinuities (discussed in chapter 2) between normative and descriptive thought. Of course Ridge argues that these views are not, in the end, correct. More precisely, he argues that going ecumenical won’t help the cognitivist – the case against ecumenical cognitivism still depends in part on cognitivist views facing certain familiar problems (e.g., in relation to explaining normative supervenience) which are not the focus of discussion in this book. I must say that I found the arguments in this chapter quite convincing, and so this isn’t a very critical ‘critical summary.’ But at least it’s a summary. Well, kind of. I also try to highlight some interesting claims which I hope others will deem questionable, but if you’ve read the chapter you’ll know where the most interesting action is here. So, you could just skip reading the rest of my summary and proceed to try to explain why Ridge’s arguments against ecumenical cognitivism are problematic (or especially, interestingly awesome, or whatever).

Ridge first offers a neat characterization of cognitivism and ecumenical cognitivism (p. 80):

(Cognitivism) Normative claims express beliefs with genuinely representational contents, such that the content in question is the same as the content of the claim which expresses the belief.

(Ecumenical Cognitivism) Normative claims express beliefs with genuinely representational contents, such that the content in question is the same as the content of the claim which expresses the belief, and they also express, in some interesting sense, desire-like states.

We may (but need not) understand the sense in which normative claims express beliefs in a ‘deflationary’ way, so that a claim ‘p’ expresses a belief that p if and only if they have the same content.

There are two forms of ecumenical cognitivism: Implicative Ecumenical Cognitivism and Judgment-Individuating Ecumenical Cognitivism, and these can be further divided into two subclasses. We get the following views:

(Conversationally Implicative Ecumenical Cognitivism) A normative claim ‘p’ conversationally implicates (in conversational contexts of certain interesting kinds) that the speaker is in a certain kind of desire-like state.

(Conventionally Implicative Ecumenical Cognitivism) A normative claim ‘p’ conventionally implicates that the speaker is in a certain kind of desire-like state.

(Non-Constitutive Judgment-Individuating Ecumenical Cognitivism) The desire-like state expressed by a normative claim ‘p’ is not a part of the judgment that p, but being in the relevant desire-like state is a necessary condition for counting as making the judgment in question.

(Constitutive Judgment-Individuating Ecumenical Cognitivism) The desire-like state expressed by a normative claim ‘p’ is a part of the judgment that p.

I hope that’s roughly right. Also, Ridge (p. 85) notes, in passing, yet another view, Directly Implicative Ecumenical Cognitivism, according to which “normative utterances somehow directly express desire-like states of mind, where direct expression is contrasted with expression via the implicature of the content that one is in such-and-such state of mind” (and being in the relevant desire-like state is not necessary in order to make the corresponding normative judgment).

Ridge explains all these views in some more detail (with the exception of the directly implicative view) and characterizes some specific variants of them (at least those defended by Stephen Finlay, David Copp, Stephen Barker, Daniel Boisvert, and Jon Tresan). I found nothing wrong with these explanations and characterizations, but I should add that it’s been a while since I read some of the relevant papers (and I’ve yet to read what seems like a super interesting new book from Finlay). If some of you have some relevant concerns, I hope you’ll bring them up. (I was initially surprised about Ridge’s classifying Jackson & Pettit 1995 as defending a judgment-individuating ecumenical view of sorts, but yeah, that paper apparently suggests, very roughly, that normative thinkers normally accept normative claims in a way which involves having suitable desires. Also, incidentally, I seem to recall that G. H. von Wright makes, in a paper from 1953 or 1954 (written only in Swedish), some remarks which suggest a ‘pluralist’ view such as the one Ridge attributes to Edwards.) Anyway, Ridge has some interesting criticisms to offer against the different forms of ecumenical cognitivism. So, what’s supposed to be wrong with them?

The problem with the implicative versions of ecumenical expressivism is, in a nutshell, that they do not explain the way that normative thought is action-guiding (and acrimonious, and also affect-implicating – although I think that it is a bit hard to evaluate the competing explanations for this last feature of normative thought at this point, given that the connection to affect is contingent and so doesn’t perhaps seem quite as problematic for a cognitivist to account for, and that the expressivist explanation hasn’t really been laid out in any detail, yet, either). As Ridge (p. 87) puts it, on the implicative views, “while my publicly making a normative claim may commit me to a suitably desire-like state of mind, my judgment does not.”

Ridge focuses on internalism and on Copp’s attempts at a ‘debunking explanation’ of the intuitions that would seem to support a stronger connection between normative (or perhaps more accurately: moral) judgment and motivation than can be captured on the implicative views. Ridge registers five concerns with the Copp-style idea (pp. 88–89). There’s no point in my summarizing them. It’s a rather sweeping dismissal of the implicative views, but I find it persuasive. Obviously, these are some of the passages that I’m hoping others will find something critical to say about. (How about disagreement? Well, presumably the idea is that the ecumenical views face the kinds of problems discussed in chapter 2, and that appealing to desire-like states being expressed by the public normative claims won’t be of any help to the cognitivist.)

Ridge then proceeds to discuss judgment-individuating ecumenical cognitivism. Here, Ridge suggests, going ecumenical might really provide the cognitivist with some interesting resources. He now focuses on disagreement, but presumably the thought is that the judgment-individuating views really might have an edge over competing forms of cognitivism when it comes to explaining the intimate connections between normative thought and motivation. However, disagreement is, in any case, a source of problems for the cognitivist. As we learned in chapter 2, all the cognitivist views have problems with disagreement. Very roughly, sui generis normative features are too weird, and analytic reductionism cannot make adequate sense of disagreement over the normative matters between thinkers who agree on the non-normative stuff. The extra resources of the ecumenical views might, though, help a little bit when it comes to synthetic reductionist (or contextualist) views’ problems with regard to making sense of our having genuine disagreements on normative issues, and not talking past each other, under certain sorts of circumstances (Hare’s cannibals, Moral Twin Earth, etc.). So, let’s suppose that X’s use of ‘good’ is in some suitable way causally regulated by Fness, and Y’s use of ‘good’ by Gness. X says (and thinks that) A is good, Y says (and thinks that) it is not – they end up speaking past each other and not really disagreeing, it seems. Except that according to the judgment-individuating ecumenical views, X is ‘for’ A, while Y is in some conflicting desire-like state. So perhaps they have a ‘disagreement in attitude.’ If expressivists can appeal to this idea, then why not others? Or that’s roughly the idea. The problem with this move is a familiar one: Y should be able to signal her disagreement with X by saying that what X says/thinks is not true. However, according to the relevant cognitivist view, it would seem to be appropriate for Y to say something along the lines of ‘What X says is true, but I disagree with her,’ which doesn’t really seem to make any sense.

Ridge writes, on p. 92, that he has argued (in chapter 2) that “all of the synthetic reductionist semantics on offer” have the consequence that X and Y may both speak/think truly. Now, that seems questionable, as Ridge only very briefly outlines a ‘causal regulation’ view in chapter 2 (pp. 75–76), and there’s no discussion of the literature that is critical of Horgan & Timmons (with which Ridge undoubtedly is familiar). Myself, I’d guess that it may very well be that the relevant, more sophisticated attempts at suitable synthetic reductionist semantics either end up being relevantly similar to the kind of causal regulation view that Ridge discusses, or they end up being relevantly similar to the non-naturalist views. Also, perhaps any synthetic reductionist view which secures genuine disagreement between X and Y just in virtue of their beliefs will have trouble accounting for the ‘acrimonious’ features of normative thought. But I thought I’d mention this, anyway – just in case someone would be inclined to try to defend synthetic reductionism on this score.

Suppose, though, that the synthetic reductionist attempts to appeal to disagreement in attitude. The very interesting, final part of this chapter discusses a possible way of trying to respond to the problem that Ridge presses in relation to the misalignment between attributions of truth and disagreement. The response in question is due to Gunnar Björnsson, Stephen Finlay and Alexander Almér (ABF). The basic idea is that when Y says/thinks that what X says is not true, she need not be assessing as false the same proposition that X’s claim has expressed. Rather, she is assessing as false the proposition that would be expressed by the claim that she herself would make using the sentence ‘A is good.’ This is so, roughly, because when we converse or think about normative matters our interest normally is in our own values. So, that’s why it would not be okay for Y to say/think ‘X’s belief is true, but I disagree.’ I suppose one could raise questions about how exactly this explanation is supposed to work. Ridge’s point, however, is that even if this explanation did work in some contexts, we’d expect there to be some contexts in which Y could make non-deviant claims attributing truth to X’s views while signaling disagreement. Something like ‘X’s belief about A is quite literally true, and I disagree with it,’ perhaps even coupled with ‘Oh, and by the way, let me be clear that I have no desire to promote my values,’ should seem fine. But it doesn’t. So, ABF’s defense strategy generates wrong kind of predictions, and isn’t satisfying. I’m quite convinced, but although I cannot think of anything to say in defense of ABF, I’m sure there’s more to be said here.

Tuesday, May 6, 2014

Chapter 2: Normative thought and discourse: Affective, Action-Guiding, and Acrimonious



In this chapter, Ridge tries to identify three features of normative thought and discourse: action-guiding, affective, and acrimonious. This chapter, like the last, has a lot of content, and so I'll be able only to briefly summarise some highlights.

1. Action-guiding
Ridge starts by giving three arguments against externalism (48-9), understood as the view that there is no essential connection between normative judgement and motivation, but instead only a contingent connection, mediated by a desire to do what one ought to do. As he acknowledges, he here moves quite quickly over a large debate, and I doubt that externalists will be swayed by his arguments. (If people are interested, I can expand in comments.)

Having rejected externalism, Ridge endorses internalism. Ridge glosses this as CJI, the claim that first-person normative judgements are necessarily capable of motivating without the help of any independent desire (50). Ridge then addresses the possibility of amoralists, who are not at all moved by their moral judgements. The discussion largely focuses on work by Shaun Nichols apparently showing that everyday speakers think that amoralists are possible. Ridge presents a series of (compelling) arguments that suggest that Nichols' study is of relatively limited evidential value (52-3). Ridge next presents a series of arguments that aim to defend CJI from worries about amoralists. The third of Ridge's replies has always seemed to me exactly right: it's unhelpful that this debate focuses on amoralists. If amoralists think that morality is not normatively binding, then the possibility of their existence tells us little about normative judgements (55). We should instead focus on 'anormativists' who are not moved by their normative judgements. Here, some kind of internalism is highly compelling. Ridge ends this section with a further interesting argument: that normative judgements must be capable of motivating us, otherwise we could not be rationally required to be motivated by them (56-7).

One thing that seemed to slip in and out of the discussion here was the question of just how bold Ridge's formulation of judgement internalism is supposed to be. If it's merely the claim that - as stated - normative judgements are capable of motivating us to act, then amoralists don't threaten the view in the slightest: this formulation of judgement internalism is perfectly consistent with the possibility that normative judgements don't always exercise their motivational capacity. So I'm not sure if Ridge (a) actually wants some bolder formulation of judgement internalism, or (b) should have mentioned this easy reply. (Disclosure: I have work-in-progress in which I defend this kind of internalism as the best way to formulate the view, in part for this kind of reason.)

2. Affective
In this (relatively short) section, Ridge wants to argue that there is a connection between normative judgement and affect. Interestingly, he concedes that this connection may be a contingent feature of human nature rather than a truth about normative judgement as such (58) - I'll be interested to see later why he thinks this claim is still relevant for the rest of the book. He starts with some empirical evidence that demonstrate the connection between normative judgement and affect (58-9). Next, he considers whether these studies support some kind of naive subjectivism, and endorses the familiar argument that such views cannot do justice to truths about disagreement (60-3). Perhaps the most interesting part of this discussion was the discussion of Prinz's more sophisticated subjectivist view.

3. Acrimonious
Finally, in this section, Ridge examines the nature of normative disagreement. First, he surveys some familiar cases of normative disagreement (64-6). Ridge presents two reasons to think that such disagreement is not always generated by disagreement over the non-normative facts (66). He then wants to argue that such disagreement is not always generated by conceptual confusion (67).

Here the chapter seems to take an unspoken change of focus: we stop examining the extent of normative disagreement, and instead start to examine how such apparent disagreement is possible, given that people share a concept only if they share criteria for applying it (from 67, bottom). Of course, we might share criteria for applying a concept but nonetheless apply it differently to one another if, say, we disagree about the evidence, or one of us is non-ideal in some manner. But Ridge argues that these factors don't explain normative disagreement (68-9). Instead, Ridge argues that we should think that competence with non-normative concepts is very different from competence with normative concepts: the requirement that we must share criteria for applying concepts applies only to non-normative concepts (68).

One might think that people do share criteria for applying normative concepts, but that disagreement arises only because we are non-ideal in some relevant manner. For example (and only an example), someone might claim that ideal speakers would agree about the application of the predicate ‘good’, and that we don’t only because we are non-ideal in that we have had poor moral education (cf. Aristotle, McDowell…). Ridge doesn't seem to say too much about this general possibility. Perhaps he doesn’t say much about this because he thinks that those sympathetic to such a view are more likely to be non-naturalist realists, and Ridge next presents independent arguments against such views (70-1). This went very swiftly, though I confess (despite myself) that I liked the way he expressed the motivation worry at the top of 71.

Since non-naturalism is often motivated by Moore's open question argument, Ridge next turns to see how else we might respond to that argument. So far as I can see, though we get onto this topic by a series of connections that are individually intelligible, by this point the chapter is quite far from where it began. I'd be interested to hear if I've missed something about how this all hangs together.

On the open question argument, one response is some kind of analytic reductionism that takes the relevant reduction to be non-obvious. Normative functionalists hold such a view, but Ridge argues that their view faces a dilemma (71-5): either the relevant platitudes that supposedly determine reference are so modest that they fail to fix reference, or else they are so bold that they fix reference but wrongly entail that many everyday speakers don't have possession of the relevant concepts.

Finally, we address synthetic reductionism, and Ridge rehearses the familiar worry that such views make disagreement across linguistic communities impossible (75-6).